Iris Murdoch is best-known as
a novelist but she was also a professional philosopher. Here she is in The
Sovereignty of the Good (1970), reflecting on the transformative power
of attention, in this case attention to the natural world:
I am looking out of my window in an anxious and resentful state of mind,
oblivious of my surroundings, brooding perhaps on some damage done to my
prestige. Then suddenly I observe a hovering kestrel. In a moment everything is
altered. The brooding self with its hurt vanity has disappeared. There is
nothing now but kestrel.
The passage looks back to a long tradition of
reflections about the restorative powers of nature, but it also looks forward
to what has, in recent years, become a torrent of public affirmations of nature
as therapy. The idea is now almost a commonplace: confirmed by the moving
testimony of many personal memoirs; supported by scientific research that
quantifies the effects on our mental and physical health; and enthusiastically
endorsed by all the big wildlife and conservation bodies. Indeed, the UK
government itself confidently announces in its new Environment Bill: ‘Nature
plays a vital role in public health and wellbeing.’ So, it’s official. Nature
is good for you. But is it really so simple? Are they all talking about the
same ‘nature’ and the same human needs? And where does ‘human nature’ come into
it? I think Murdoch points us to a different and deeper insight.
It’s easy to believe in a general way in the
positive benefits of nature. Don’t we all instinctively feel better for a walk
in the fresh air, a view of some greenery and the sound of bird song? Even more
so, surely, if we actively explore the natural world and engage with it in some
way. I feel that myself, very strongly. Indeed, I’m co-author with two other
naturalists, Michael McCarthy and Peter Marren, of a recent book, The
Consolation of Nature (2020), sharing just such experiences.
But in writing for this book, even as I found myself more than ever absorbed in
the wonders and delights of nature, I grew increasingly sceptical about its
proclaimed status as primarily a medical commodity.
To begin with, can nature really provide
experiences that are either a necessary or a sufficient condition of enjoying
good health?
Not a necessary condition, surely, since we can all
think of people in excellent physical and psychological health who have little
interest in nature. Nor a sufficient condition either, since conversely there
are many people devoted to nature who are not thereby protected from serious
illness, depression or stress. Richard Mabey’s book Nature
Cure (2005) is regularly invoked as the inspiration for a whole genre
of ‘nature therapy’ memoirs, celebrating the healing power of nature against
various forms of bereavement, depression, addiction and despair. But,
in fact, though Mabey’s work is a literary classic by a great naturalist, its
title is somewhat misleading. His severe depression prevented him
from responding as he usually did to nature, and it was only after he
began to be cured that he could again enjoy what had been a lifelong passion.
The other titles, too, all tell more complicated personal stories, with a range
of (sometimes unhappy) outcomes. The idea of a genre of effective nature cure
books, in short, is more of a publisher’s invention than a reliable medical
library.
What these books do demonstrate, however, is that there’s no ‘nature pill’ or ‘green Prozac’ you can simply take for a quick fix. It doesn’t work that way. Which way it does work, though, is much harder to say. If we’re now considering the much more modest claim that it helps some people, some of the time, and in some respects, we need to be more specific. Does it make a difference, for example, which part or aspect of nature we’re exposed to? Are plants and birds better for us than mammals or insects? Some birds better than others? Wild or tame? Helen Macdonald, after all, the author of another literary tour de force, H is for Hawk (2014), found her solace in a captive bird. How about slime-moulds, snakes and spiders? Or bacteria and viruses – all part of nature? And a key theme in much current environmental rhetoric is to emphasise that we ourselves are also inextricably a part of nature. But aren’t other people part of what we’re trying to avoid in getting more in touch with nature and the wild …?
Ever since Roger Ulrich’s paper was
published in the journal Science in 1984, demonstrating that
patients recovering from gall bladder surgery made substantially quicker and
better recoveries if they had a view from their beds looking outward to trees
and greenery rather than inward to the brick walls of the ward, scientists have
been trying to isolate such variables. Ulrich himself pointed to some of the
difficulties in identifying the crucial factors, however. His paper is now more
cited than read, but he was careful to emphasise its limitations. Would it have
made a difference if those brick walls had attractive pictures on them? Was it
the trees that made the difference to the lucky patients with an outside view,
or would a view of inanimate nature – sky, mountains or water – have done so as
well? How would they have reacted to a busy urban street scene? Was their main
problem boredom or anxiety?
Subsequent studies have gone some way to answering
such questions, in particular through the measurement of associated
physiological phenomena such as blood-pressure levels and neurochemical rewards
in the form of serotonin, dopamine and endorphins. It’s become something of an
industry, in fact. If you Google ‘scientific studies of nature and health’, you
will in less than a second get more than 1 billion results,
referencing research in universities worldwide, both in mainline departments of
biological, medical and environmental studies and in such emerging
sub-disciplines as ecopsychology and ecotherapy. To the extent that such
studies rely on patients’ own reports of their sense of wellbeing, however, the
headline results remain very generic. What does it really mean, for example, to
be told: ‘Go Wild – And Feel 30 Per Cent Healthier And Significantly
Happier’, as The Sunday Times said on 31 May 2020,
reporting on research from
Derby University? Or ‘How Much Nature Is Enough? 120 Minutes A Week,
Doctors Say’ as The New York Times said on 13
June 2019, reporting the study done
at Exeter University? We are still a very long way from a functional analysis
of what specific items in ‘nature’ produce what effects.
But there’s a larger problem,
too, in this line of thought. It treats such medical rewards as just one more
of the ‘services’ we receive from the natural world, alongside the pollination
of our crops, waste recycling, carbon capture, flood protection, ecotourism and
so on. The environmentalist Tony Juniper wrote a very persuasive book, What
Has Nature Ever Done for Us? (2013), quantifying such benefits in
monetary terms in order to attract the sympathetic attention of policymakers.
The demonstration of these natural services has become another minor publishing
industry, establishing important evidence for conservationists to deploy in
their campaigns.
These might indeed be the only arguments that have decisive political force, but effective arguments aren’t the same as real reasons. These utilitarian considerations are not why we thrill to a nightingale’s song, a peacock butterfly’s fragile beauty or a bluebell wood in spring. As individuals, we respond to such things directly and for their own sakes, not after or because of some financial calculation. To appreciate the natural world in a sense of wonder, awe, curiosity, joy or affinity is to recognise an intrinsic value, not an instrumental one. Henry David Thoreau made a similar point in his graduation address at Harvard College in 1837:
This curious world which we inhabit is more wonderful than it is
convenient; more beautiful than it is useful; it is more to be admired and
enjoyed than used.
It’s the same with creative work in art, music,
poetry and science, surely. They can all be demonstrated to bring quantifiable
public benefits, ranging from cultural tourism to various practical
applications. But such beneficial consequences are far from fully explaining
the motivations of the practitioners themselves.
Indeed, logic itself requires that there must be
goods with intrinsic value that need no further justification. Something can be
good as a means only if there are some other things that are good as ends,
otherwise the question ‘Good for what?’ leads to an infinite regress. Beauty,
truth and happiness are all examples of intrinsic goods. And it’s the common
experience, as well as the credo of naturalists, that the natural world offers
us one form of direct access to such values.
But there’s a final catch, Murdoch’s catch. She
goes on from the passage I quoted at the beginning to say:
A self-directed enjoyment of nature seems to me to be something forced.
More naturally, as well as more properly, we take a self-forgetful pleasure in
the sheer alien pointless independent existence of animals, birds, stones and
trees.
The authors of the ‘nature cure’
books were discovering that nature could offer some balm for their ills. But,
to find that relief, they had to attend directly to what they could see, hear,
touch or smell; and then, if they were lucky, the psychological and other
benefits might follow. It’s a corner-of-the-eye thing. There’s no point in
putting beauty, wonder, inspiration, understanding and the other positive experiences
we rightly associate with nature on some sort of ‘to do’ list. They are what
philosophers call ‘supervenient’ on the experiences themselves. Try too hard
and you’ll fail. It’s a subtle distinction but a fundamental one. It’s the act
of attention, as Murdoch says, that takes you out of yourself and so delivers
delights that a preoccupation with self would deny you. You have to lose
yourself to find yourself.
Nature is good for you. That doesn’t mean we should prescribe it | Psyche Ideas
No comments:
Post a Comment